Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making
The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making
The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making
Ebook2,588 pages29 hours

The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

  • A comprehensive, up-to-date examination of the most important theory, concepts, methodological approaches, and applications in the burgeoning field of judgment and decision making (JDM)
  • Emphasizes the growth of JDM applications with chapters devoted to medical decision making, decision making and the law, consumer behavior, and more
  • Addresses controversial topics from multiple perspectives – such as choice from description versus choice from experience – and contrasts between empirical methodologies employed in behavioral
    economics and psychology
  • Brings together a multi-disciplinary group of contributors from across the social sciences, including psychology, economics, marketing, finance, public policy, sociology, and philosophy

2 Volumes
LanguageEnglish
PublisherWiley
Release dateNov 30, 2015
ISBN9781118912799
The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making

Related to The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making

Related ebooks

Psychology For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making - Gideon Keren

    Table of Contents

    Cover

    Volume 1

    Title Page

    Contributors

    1 A Bird’s-Eye View of the History of Judgment and Decision Making

    Some Early Historical Milestones

    The Initial Period, 1954–1972 (Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making, 1974)

    The Second Period (1972–1986) (Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making, 1988)

    The Third Period (1986–2002) (Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making, 2004)

    The Fourth Period (2002–2014) (Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making, 2015)

    A Bird’s-Eye View

    References

    Part I: The Multiple Facets of Judgment and Decision Making: Traditional Themes

    2 Decision Under Risk: From the Field to the Laboratory and Back

    Introduction: From the Field to the Laboratory

    Modeling Risky Choice

    Alternative Behavioral Models of Risky Choice

    From the Laboratory to the Field

    Conclusion

    Acknowledgments

    References

    3 Ambiguity Attitudes

    Introduction

    Ellsberg Urns and Other Operationalizations of Ambiguity

    Stylized Facts From Laboratory Experiments

    Evidence on External Validity of Laboratory Measures

    Conclusion and Outlook

    Acknowledgments

    References

    4 Multialternative Choice Models

    Introduction

    Facets of the Choice Situation

    Process Distinctions

    Choice Models

    Summary

    References

    5 The Psychology of Intertemporal Preferences

    Introduction

    Discounting Behavior

    Psychological Determinants

    Applications of Discounting to Decision Making

    Conclusions

    Acknowledgments

    References

    6 Overprecision in Judgment

    Introduction

    Research Paradigms

    The Balance of the Evidence

    Ecological Evidence of Overprecision

    Moderators of Overprecision

    Explanations

    Underprecision

    Debiasing Overprecision

    Incentive-Compatible Scoring Rules for Eliciting Precision in Judgments

    (Mis)Perceiving Expressions of Confidence

    Future Research

    Coda

    References

    Part II: Relatively New Themes in Judgment and Decision Making

    7 Joint versus Separate Modes of Evaluation: Theory and Practice

    Introduction

    Clarifying Several Issues Concerning Evaluation Mode

    General Evaluability Theory

    Implications of Evaluation Mode and Evaluability

    References

    8 Decisions from Experience

    Introduction

    The Description–Experience Gap in Risky Choice

    Sampling Error and the Description–Experience Gap

    Search Policies and the Description–Experience Gap

    The Anatomy of Search in the Sampling Paradigm

    Models of Decisions From Experience

    Probability Weighting and the Description–Experience Gap

    Beyond Monetary Gambles and Beyond a Simple Dichotomy

    The Description–Experience Gap and Risk Communication

    Let Us Not Give Descriptions Short Shrift

    Conclusions

    Acknowledgments

    References

    9 Neurosciences Contribution to Judgment and Decision Making: Opportunities and Limitations

    Introduction

    Methods

    Individual Decision Making

    Social Decision Making

    Limitations

    The Future

    References

    10 Utility: Anticipated, Experienced, and Remembered

    Historical Background

    Components and Judgments of Experienced Utility

    Measuring Instant and Total Utility

    Context Dependence

    Maximization Failures

    Summary

    Acknowledgments

    References

    Part III: New Psychological Takes on Judgment and Decision Making

    11 Under the Influence and Unaware: Unconscious Processing During Encoding, Retrieval, and Weighting in Judgment

    Introduction

    Defining Unconscious Influences

    Unconscious Influences on Three Aspects of Judgment

    A Controversy: Questioning Unconscious Effects on Judgment

    Scaling Up Models of Unconscious Decision Making

    Conclusion

    Acknowledgments

    References

    12 Metacognition: Decision making Processes in Self-monitoring and Self-regulation

    Introduction

    Metacognitive Processes During Learning

    Metacognitive Processes During Remembering

    Retrospective Confidence in One's Answers and Judgments

    Conclusions

    Acknowledgments

    References

    13 Information Sampling and Reasoning Biases: Implications for Research in Judgment and Decision Making

    Introduction

    Manifold Reasons for Biased Sampling

    Sampling Errors and Biases in Judgment and Decision Making

    The Ideal of Unbiased Sampling in a Representative Design

    Unequal Sample Size as a Source of Illusions

    Impact of Hedonic Sampling

    Unbiased Sampling as a Source of Bias: The World We Live In

    Concluding Remark

    Acknowledgment

    References

    14 On the Psychology of Near and Far: A Construal Level Theoretic Approach

    Introduction

    Mentally Traveling Across Psychological Distance

    On High-Level and Low-Level Features

    Overview of Empirical Evidence

    Impact of Distance-Dependent Construal on Prediction

    Impact of Distance-Dependent Construal on Preferences

    Distinguishing CLT from Other Theoretical Approaches

    Concluding Thoughts

    References

    15 Optimism Biases: Types and Causes

    Introduction

    Terms and Effects

    Optimism in Studies Involving Self–Other Comparisons

    The Desirability Bias

    Conclusion

    Acknowledgment

    References

    16 Culture and Judgment and Decision Making

    Introduction

    Risky Decision Making

    Risk Perception

    Intertemporal Choice

    Consistency Between Preferences and Choices

    Causal Attributions

    Conflict Decisions

    Confidence Judgments

    Optimism

    What Counts as a Decision?

    Insights from the Constructivist Approach to Culture and JDM

    Future Research Directions

    Conclusion

    References

    17 Moral Judgment and Decision Making

    Introduction

    Attempts to Understand Moral Judgment and Decision Making: Major Research Themes and Their Explananda

    Methodological Desiderata

    Understudied Areas

    Concluding Remarks

    Acknowledgments

    References

    Volume 2

    Title Page

    Contributors

    Part IV: Old Issues Revisited

    18 Time-pressure Perception and Decision Making

    Introduction

    Impact of Time Constraints on Decision Making

    Time-Pressure Perceptions

    Time-Pressure Applications

    Conclusion

    References

    19 Cognitive Hierarchy Process Models of Strategic Thinking in Games

    Introduction

    Background: What are Games, and What is Game Theory?

    Conclusions

    Acknowledgments

    References

    20 Framing of Numerical Quantities

    Introduction

    Origins and definitions

    Chapter themes

    Risky-Choice Framing

    Attribute Framing

    Frames as Part of the Communication Process

    Who is Susceptible to Framing?

    Framing on Unipolar Scales

    Suggestions for Future Research

    Conclusions

    References

    21 Causal Thinking in Judgments

    Introduction

    Basic Causal Concepts and Distinctions

    Fundamental Properties of Causal Reasoning

    Elementary Causal Inferences

    Probabilities From Causes

    Causal Schemas

    Predictions and Diagnoses in Multiple Cause–Effect Schemas

    Judgments of Causes and Effects in a Common-Effect Schema

    Scenarios and Multi-Causal Situation Models

    Causal Cognitions Play a Major Role in Many Researched Judgments

    Causal Reasoning in Choices and Decisions

    So what?

    Acknowledgments

    References

    22 Learning Models in Decision Making

    Introduction

    Learning and Risk Taking

    Strategy Selection

    Summary and Conclusion

    References

    23 Variability, Noise, and Error in Decision Making Under Risk

    Introduction

    Basic Framework

    Extraneous Noise/Error

    Intrinsic Variability

    Interactions Between Different Approaches and Challenges for the Future

    Concluding Remarks

    Acknowledgments

    References

    24 Expertise in Decision Making

    Introduction

    Defining Expertise

    Research on Expertise: Expertise is Schematic

    The Role of the Environment in the Development of Expertise

    Is General Decision Making Expertise Possible?

    Shortcomings of Expertise

    Using Expertise

    Future Directions

    References

    Part V: Applications

    25 Changing Behavior Beyond the Here and Now

    Introduction

    Intervention–Behavior Lag

    Marginal Benefit to Continued Treatment

    Persistence

    Conclusion

    Acknowledgments

    References

    26 Decision Making and the Law: Truth Barriers

    Introduction

    The Law Hinders Accurate Decision Making

    Intellectual Deficits of Legal Participants: Harmful Effects of Innumeracy

    Cognitive Biases

    Conclusion

    References

    27 Medical Decision Making

    Introduction

    Biases and Heuristics and the Effect of Debiasing

    The Role of Uncertainty

    The Role of Affect

    Affective Forecasting

    Decisions for Oneself Versus Decisions for Others

    Nudging

    Literacy and Numeracy

    Support for Complex Decisions: Patient Decision Aids

    Areas for Future Research

    References

    28 Behavioral Economics: Economics as a Psychological Discipline

    Introduction

    Public and Health Economics

    Industrial Organization and Consumer Decision Making

    Labor and Education Economics

    Development Economics

    Urban and Environmental Economics

    Macroeconomics

    Conclusion

    References

    29 Negotiation and Conflict Resolution: A Behavioral Decision Research Perspective

    Introduction

    The Behavioral Decision Research Approach

    Beyond Cognition: Affect and Motivation in Negotiation

    Beyond Profit Maximization: Negotiators’ Relational Outcomes

    Incorporating the BDR Approach to the Study of Relational Outcomes

    Conclusion

    References

    30 Decision Making in Groups and Organizations

    Introduction

    Simple Aggregation

    Aggregation with Limited Information Exchange

    Judge–Advisor Systems

    Fully Interacting Groups

    Technology and the Future of Group Decision Making

    References

    31 Consumer Decision Making

    Introduction

    Consumer Decision Making as an Interdisciplinary Application Area

    Development of the Field of Consumer Decision Making

    Recent Themes in Consumer Decision Making

    Conclusion

    Acknowledgment

    References

    Part VI: Improving Decision Making

    32 Decision Technologies

    Introduction

    Decision Trees

    Assessing Probabilities for Continuous and Discrete Cases

    Valuing Outcomes

    Multiple Objective Decisions Under Certainty with Swing Weights

    Conclusion

    References

    33 A User’s Guide to Debiasing

    Introduction

    Sources of Bias

    Decision Readiness

    Modify the Person

    Modify the Environment

    Organizational Cognitive Repairs

    Choosing a Debiasing Strategy

    An Example

    Final Remarks

    References

    34 What’s a Good Decision? Issues in Assessing Procedural and Ecological Quality

    Introduction

    The Simplicity of Savage

    Acknowledgments

    References

    Part VII: Summary

    35 A Final Glance Backwards and a Suggestive Glimpse Forwards

    Introduction

    The Gambling Paradigm

    Illustration of Alternative Paradigms

    The Current State of the Field

    References

    Author Index

    Subject Index

    End User License Agreement

    List of Tables

    Chapter 02

    Table 2.1 Fourfold Pattern of Risk Attitudes.

    Table 2.2 Risk Aversion for Mixed (Gain–Loss) Gambles.

    Chapter 03

    Table 3.1 Ellsberg two-color problem.

    Table 3.2 Ellsberg three-color problem.

    Table 3.3 10-number urns and (un)likely events.

    Table 3.4 Ambiguity premia in Ellsberg tasks for gains.

    Chapter 11

    Table 11.1 Examples of unconscious influences on encoding, retrieval, and weighting aspects of information processing.

    Chapter 19

    Table 19.1 A stag hunt or assurance game with multiple Nash equilibria.

    Table 19.2 Payoffs in betting-on-rationality game, predictions (Nash and CH), and results from classroom demonstrations in 2006–2008.

    Table 19.3a Payoffs and random states for players P1, P2 in a betting game.

    Table 19.3b Payoff lookups for P2 in information set {A}.

    Table 19.3c Payoff lookups for P2 in information set {A,B}.

    Table 19.3d Payoff lookups for P2 in information set {B,C}.

    Chapter 22

    Table 22.1 Parameters of the expectancy valence model.

    Table 22.2 Parameters of the Bayesian sequential risk-taking model.

    Chapter 23

    Table 23.1 Probabilities of choice at different levels of sure payoff.

    Table 23.2 Probabilities of choice at different probabilities of higher payoff.

    Table 23.3 Three choices with money payoffs.

    Table 23.4 Common ratio effect pairs.

    Table 23.5 Six transitive orderings for {X, Y, Z}.

    Chapter 25

    Table 25.1 Features likely to bridge time.

    Table 25.2 Features likely to produce marginal benefits to continued treatment.

    Table 25.3 Pathways to persistence.

    Chapter 34

    Table 34.1 Stages of decision processes and questions relevant to procedural and ecological quality.

    List of Illustrations

    Chapter 01

    Figure 1.1 Contents of a hypothetical JDM handbook for the period 1954–1972.

    Figure 1.2 Contents of a hypothetical JDM handbook for the period 1972–1986.

    Figure 1.3 Contents of JDM handbook for the period 1986–2002 (Koehler & Harvey, 2004).

    Chapter 02

    Figure 2.1 A concave utility function over states of wealth that is characterized by diminishing marginal utility.

    Figure 2.2 A visual depiction of how a concave utility function predicts risk aversion in the case of the choice of {gain $50 for sure} over {a 50% chance to gain $100 or else gain nothing}.

    Figure 2.3 A representative value function from prospect theory depicting the subjective value of money gained or lost relative to a reference point.

    Figure 2.4 A representative probability weighting function from prospect theory depicting the impact of various probabilities on the valuation of a prospect.

    Figure 2.5 Framework for building a model of behavior, consisting of three steps of model building (baseline model, model variables, model parameters) and three levels of analysis (typical behavior, individual differences, state differences).

    Chapter 04

    Figure 4.1 Two-attribute choice space with equal-weighting vector and equipreference contour on which both target (T) and competitor (C) alternatives are located. The D alternatives reflect different contextual (decoy) alternatives designed to favor T. Shaded areas indicate values dominated by T, C, or both.

    Figure 4.2 Connectionist depiction of MDFT applied to three alternatives, target (T), competitor (C), and decoy alternative (D).

    Chapter 07

    Figure 7.1 A graphic illustration of factors influencing evaluability and hence value sensitivity.

    Figure 7.2 Hypothesized value function, temporal discounting function, and probability weighting function under joint evaluation (JE) and single evaluation (SE).

    Chapter 08

    Figure 8.1 How to study decisions from description and experience? The choice task in decisions from description (upper panel) often consists of two lotteries with explicitly stated outcomes and probabilities. In research on decisions from experience (lower panel), three paradigms (and hybrids thereof) have been employed: The sampling paradigm includes an initial sampling stage (represented by seven fictitious draws) during which the participant explores two payoff distributions by clicking on one of two buttons on a computer screen (light gray screen). After terminating sampling, the participant sees a choice screen (here shown in dark gray) and is asked to draw once for real. The buttons chosen during sampling (exploration) and choice (exploitation) are hatched diagonally. The partial-feedback paradigm merges sampling and choice, and each draw simultaneously represents exploration and exploitation. The participant receives feedback on the obtained payoff after each draw (hatched box). The full-feedback paradigm additionally reveals the forgone payoff (i.e., the payoff that the participant would have received had he or she chosen the other option; white box).

    Figure 8.2 The description–experience gap. Proportion of choices of the risky option as a function of the probability of the more desirable outcome in 6 of 120 problems studied in Erev et al.’s (2010) choice-prediction competition. Each presents a choice between a risky option and a safe option. The decision problems and the expected values of the risky options are displayed below the graph. Each problem was studied using the four paradigms displayed in Figure 1.

    Figure 8.3 The coupling of sampling and decision strategies. Two idealized sampling strategies (a) and correlated decision strategies (b). A piecewise sampling strategy alternates back and forth between payoff distributions, whereas a comprehensive sampling strategy takes one large sample from each distribution in turn. Following sampling, participants make a decision about which distribution they prefer. A roundwise decision strategy compares outcomes (gains and losses) over repeated rounds and chooses the distribution that yields higher rewards in most of the rounds. A summary decision strategy calculates the mean reward per distribution and chooses the option with the higher value.

    Figure 8.4 Exploration policy and the description–experience gap. Observed proportions of choices consistent with rare events receiving less impact than they deserve (relative to their objective probability) among infrequent switchers (comprehensive sampling), frequent switchers (piecewise sampling), and in the corresponding decisions from description (for details, see Hills & Hertwig, 2010). Error bars represent standard errors of the mean.

    Figure 8.5 How small samples foster discriminability (amplification effect). Experienced differences across 1,000 pairs of gambles as a function of sample size (per payoff distribution). The curves represent (a) the mean of the expected absolute difference, (b) the median of the experienced absolute difference, and (c) the first and third quartiles of the experienced absolute difference. The straight horizontal line represents the average description difference (the objective difference) based on the expected value (15.2) in the simulated ecology.

    Chapter 09

    Figure 9.1 Overview of brain areas involved in decision making. Anterior cingulate cortex (ACC); Dorsal medial prefrontal cortex (dmPFC); Ventromedial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC); Orbitofrontal cortex (OFC); Nucleus accumbens (NACC); Dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (dlPFC); Superior temporal sulcus (STS); Temporal parietal junction (TPJ).

    Chapter 10

    Figure 10.1 Utility of an experience across time.

    Figure 10.2 Mean (believed) contribution of anticipation, experience, and memory to the total utility of experiences.

    Figure 10.3 Predicted and remembered utility evaluated at t±1 rely on mental simulations of past or future experiences had at t0, corrected for differences between the context in which the experience is simulated (1) and the context in which it was or will be had (t0).

    Chapter 11

    Figure 11.1 Example of binocular rivalry stimulus; the original would present the B in cyan font color and the 4 in red font color while participants wear goggles fitted with one cyan lens and one red lens thereby presenting only the B to one eye and only the 4 to the other eye.

    Chapter 13

    Figure 13.1 Two stages of information transmission according to the cognitive-ecological approach (Fiedler & Wänke, 2009) to understanding biases in judgment and decision making.

    Figure 13.2 Graphical illustration of conditional sampling in medical diagnosis. Because false negatives have to be minimized for liability reasons, the set of cases captured by a diagnostic tests is typically more inclusive than the set of cases that actually have the disease.

    Figure 13.3 Jointly skewed frequency distributions in three dimensions (i.e., unequal frequency of positive versus negative feedback, more frequent feedback about computers than about telecommunication devices and about Provider 1 than about Provider 2 and Provider 3).

    Chapter 15

    Figure 15.1 A Taxonomy of Terms.Note: The terms in the gray boxes are specific types of empirical effects. The lines (with associated labels) represent the categories in which specific effects could be interpreted as belonging.

    Chapter 18

    Figure 18.1 Predicted time-pressure ratings from the three models for the current study. Dashed lines indicate specific predictions discussed in the text in which there is one more day required to complete a task than available.

    Figure 18.2 Mean time-pressure ratings from the current. Solid lines display the actual means and dashed lines show the predicted means from the relative ratio model.

    Chapter 19

    Figure 19.1 Choices in 2/3 of the average game, data from newspaper and magazines.

    Figure 19.2 Probability distributions of level types under different Poisson distribution averages τ.

    Figure 19.3 Predicted and observed behavior in entry games.

    Figure 19.4 Percentage frequencies of looking up different payoff cells, classified by overall lookup (MIN) and choice (Nash).

    Figure 19.5 Estimated strategic level types for each individual in two sets of 11 different games (Chong et al., 2005). Estimated types are correlated in two sets (r = .61).

    Figure 19.6 Numbers chosen in the first week of of Swedish LUPI lottery (N = approximately 350,000). Dotted line indicates mixed Nash equilibrium. Solid line indicate stochastic CH model with two free parameters. Best-fitting average steps of thinking is τ = 1.80 and λ = .0043 (logit response).

    Figure 19.7 Describing level 0–2 steps of CH thinking by response times, information lookups, and brain activity.

    Chapter 21

    Figure 21.1 A graphical causal model relating binary events relevant to ingestion and digestion in a physiological system. The graph would be a fully specified probabilistic causal model if base-rate probabilities of occurrence were supplied for the two parent events (Eating spicy food and Drinking coffee) and conditional probabilities were supplied for all the relevant links in the graph (e.g., p(Diarrhea|Indigestion)).

    Figure 21.2 Three subgraphs illustrating a causal-chain schema, a common-cause schema, and a common-effect schema.

    Chapter 22

    Figure 22.1 Comparing risk preference for gains and losses.

    Figure 22.2 Distribution the observer’s impression estimates after 10 rounds of potential interactions. The dashed line is the predicted distribution for an observer using an adaptive sampling rule and the solid line is the predicted distribution of the impressions for an observer who interacts on every round with the same person. Both observers have learning rates of φ = .5. The adaptive sampler observer has a response consistency parameter set at β = 3. The valence of the person’s behavior is modeled with a standard normal distribution.

    Figure 22.3 Mapping of the 10 studied populations according to their performance on the IGT adapted from Yechiam et al. (2005). The figure plots the difference between the given clinical population and its control group in terms of the EV model parameters measuring the attention to loss versus gain (λ) and in attention to recent outcomes (ϕ). The error bars for each difference are the standard errors of the differences. The diameter of each circle is proportional to the difference from the control group in the choice-consistency parameter; the black ring denotes the zero-difference boundary (circles smaller than the ring indicate low sensitivity).

    Figure 22.4 Beta distributions capturing different beliefs in the probability that the balloon will not explode.

    Chapter 23

    Figure 23.1 Frequency of choosing option B as option A is progressively improved.

    Figure 23.2 Superimposing a deterministic function.

    Figure 23.3 An individual’s frequency of choosing different options versus the same set of Ajs.

    Figure 23.4 One option worse in SI terms but with flatter curve.

    Figure 23.5 Three utility functions.

    Figure 23.6 Three utility functions applied to the SU choice.

    Figure 23.7 The same three utility functions applied to the SD choice.

    Figure 23.8 A binary choice. .

    Figure 23.9 A binary choice involving (something very close to) dominance. .

    Chapter 24

    Figure 24.1 The generation of collective knowledge and transmission to individuals as a critical process in expertise development.

    Chapter 27

    Figure 27.1 Example of a pictograph, also called icon array, to convey the magnitude of the benefit to be obtained from a form of adjuvant chemotherapy in breast cancer.

    Chapter 32

    Figure 32.1 Decision Tree.

    Figure 32.2 Expected monetary value calculation with product B branch pruned off of tree.

    Figure 32.3 Objectives hierarchy.

    Figure 32.4 Completed spreadsheet with overall values calculated.

    Figure 32.5 Raw weight of maximizing the quality of schools nearby reduced to 0.

    Figure 32.6 Swing weight for objective A1.3 maximize the quality of schools nearby.

    Chapter 33

    Figure 33.1 A continuum of debiasing strategies. By itself, new information is not debiasing, as shown on the far left. The other strategies depicted all contain elements of debiasing.

    Volume 1

    The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making

    Volume I

    Edited by

    Gideon Keren and George Wu

    This edition first published 2015

    © 2015 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd

    Registered Office

    John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK

    Editorial Offices

    350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148-5020, USA

    9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK

    The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK

    For details of our global editorial offices, for customer services, and for information about how to apply for permission to reuse the copyright material in this book please see our website at www.wiley.com/wiley-blackwell.

    The right of Gideon Keren and George Wu to be identified as the authors of the editorial material in this work has been asserted in accordance with the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.

    All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, without the prior permission of the publisher.

    Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may not be available in electronic books.

    Designations used by companies to distinguish their products are often claimed as trademarks. All brand names and product names used in this book are trade names, service marks, trademarks or registered trademarks of their respective owners. The publisher is not associated with any product or vendor mentioned in this book.

    Limit of Liability/Disclaimer of Warranty: While the publisher and authors have used their best efforts in preparing this book, they make no representations or warranties with respect to the accuracy or completeness of the contents of this book and specifically disclaim any implied warranties of merchantability or fitness for a particular purpose. It is sold on the understanding that the publisher is not engaged in rendering professional services and neither the publisher nor the author shall be liable for damages arising herefrom. If professional advice or other expert assistance is required, the services of a competent professional should be sought.

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    The Wiley Blackwell handbook of judgment and decision making / edited by Gideon Keren, George Wu.

    volumes cm

    Includes bibliographical references and index.

    ISBN 978-1-118-46839-5 (hardback)

    1. Decision making. 2. Judgment. I. Keren, Gideon. II. Wu, George.

    BF448.W55 2015

    153.4′6–dc23

    2015002776

    A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

    Contributors

    Sooyun Baik Organisational Behaviour Area, London Business School, UK

    Emily Balcetis Department of Psychology, New York University, USA

    Daniel M. Bartels University of Chicago, Booth School of Business, USA

    Christopher W. Bauman University of California-Irvine, Paul Merage School of Business, USA

    Lehman Benson III Department of Management and Organizations, University of Arizona, USA

    Colin F. Camerer Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences, Caltech, USA

    Jaee Cho Graduate School of Business, Columbia University, USA

    Fiery A. Cushman Harvard University, Department of Psychology, USA

    Marieke de Vries Tilburg University, the Netherlands

    Carsten Erner Anderson School of Management, University of California–Los Angeles, USA

    Daniel C. Feiler Tuck School of Business, Dartmouth College, USA

    Klaus Fiedler Department of Psychology, University of Heidelberg, Germany

    Craig R. Fox Anderson School of Management, University of California–Los Angeles, USA

    Erin Frey Harvard Business School, USA

    Kentaro Fujita Department of Psychology, The Ohio State University, USA

    Yael Granot Department of Psychology, New York University, USA

    Uriel Haran Guilford Glazer Faculty of Business and Management, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel

    Reid Hastie University of Chicago Booth Graduate School of Business, USA

    Ralph Hertwig Center for Adaptive Rationality (ARC), Max Planck Institute for Human Development, Germany

    Robin M. Hogarth Department of Economics and Business, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Spain

    Candice H. Huynh College of Business Administration, California State Polytechnic University, Pomona, USA

    L. Robin Keller Paul Merage School of Business, University of California–Irvine, USA

    Gideon Keren Department of Psychology, Tilburg University, the Netherlands

    Katharina Kluwe Department of Psychology, Loyola University Chicago, USA

    Jonathan J. Koehler Northwestern University School of Law, USA

    Asher Koriat Department of Psychology, University of Haifa, Israel

    Laura J. Kray Haas School of Business, University of California–Berkeley, USA

    Florian Kutzner Warwick Business School, University of Warwick, UK

    Richard P. Larrick Fuqua School of Business, Duke University, USA

    Nira Liberman Department of Psychology, Tel-Aviv University, Israel

    Graham Loomes Warwick Business School, University of Warwick, UK

    Mary Frances Luce Fuqua School of Business, Duke University, USA

    A. Peter McGraw University of Colorado Boulder, Leeds School of Business, USA

    John Meixner Northwestern University School of Law, USA

    Katherine L. Milkman The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania, USA

    Don A. Moore Haas School of Business, University of California–Berkeley, USA

    Carey K. Morewedge Questrom School of Business, Boston University, USA

    Michael W. Morris Graduate School of Business, Columbia University, USA

    Lisa D. Ordóñez Department of Management and Organizations, University of Arizona, USA

    Jillian O’Rourke Stuart Department of Psychology, University of Iowa, USA

    John W. Payne Fuqua School of Business, Duke University, USA

    Andrea Pittarello Department of Psychology, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel

    David A. Pizarro Cornell University, Department of Psychology, USA

    Timothy J. Pleskac Center for Adaptive Rationality, Max Planck Institute for Human Development, Germany

    Devin G. Pope University of Chicago, Booth School of Business, USA

    Todd Rogers Harvard Kennedy School, USA

    Alan G. Sanfey Donders Institute for Brain, Cognition and Behaviour, Radboud University, the Netherlands

    Krishna Savani Division of Strategy, Management, and Organisation, Nanyang Business School, Singapore

    Laura Scherer Psychological Sciences, University of Missouri, USA

    Jay Simon Defense Resources Management Institute, Naval Postgraduate School, USA

    Jack B. Soll Fuqua School of Business, Duke University, USA

    Mirre Stallen Donders Institute for Brain, Cognition and Behaviour, Radboud University, the Netherlands

    Anne M. Stiggelbout Leiden University Medical Center, the Netherlands

    Justin R. Sydnor School of Business, University of Wisconsin, USA

    Karl Halvor Teigen Department of Psychology, University of Oslo, Norway

    Elizabeth R. Tenney David Eccles School of Business, University of Utah, USA

    R. Scott Tindale Department of Psychology, Loyola University Chicago, USA

    Stefan T. Trautmann Alfred-Weber-Institute for Economics, Heidelberg University, Germany

    Yaacov Trope Department of Psychology, New York University, USA

    Oleg Urminsky University of Chicago, Booth School of Business, USA

    Gijs van de Kuilen Tilburg University, the Netherlands

    Alex B. Van Zant Haas School of Business, University of California–Berkeley, USA

    Daniel J. Walters Anderson School of Management, University of California–Los Angeles, USA

    Douglas H. Wedell Department of Psychology, University of South Carolina, USA

    Paul D. Windschitl Department of Psychology, University of Iowa, USA

    George Wu University of Chicago, Booth School of Business, USA

    Gal Zauberman Yale University, Yale School of Management, USA

    Jiao Zhang Lundquist College of Business, University of Oregon, USA

    1

    A Bird’s-Eye View of the History of Judgment and Decision Making

    Gideon Keren

    Department of Psychology, Tilburg University, the Netherlands

    George Wu

    University of Chicago, Booth School of Business, USA

    Any historical account has a subjective element in it and is thus vulnerable to the benefit of hindsight (Fischhoff, 1975; Roese & Vohs, 2012). This historical review of 60 years of judgment and decision making (JDM) research is of course no exception. Our attempt to sketch the major developments of the field since its inception is further colored by the interests and knowledge of the two authors and thus surely reflects any number of egocentric biases (Dunning & Hayes, 1996; Ross, Greene, & House, 1977). Notwithstanding, we feel that there is a high level of agreement among JDM researchers as to the main developments that have shaped the field. This chapter is an attempt to document this consensus and trace the impact of these developments on the field.

    The present handbook is the successor to the Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making that appeared in 2004. That handbook, edited by Derek Koehler and Nigel Harvey, was the first handbook of judgment and decision making. Our overview of the field is prompted by the following plausible counterfactual: What if one or more JDM handbooks had appeared prior to 2004?¹ Handbooks might (and should) alter the course of a field by making useful content accessible, providing organizing frameworks, and posing important questions (Farr, 1991). Although we recognize these important roles, our chapter is motivated by one other function of a handbook: a handbook’s editors serve as curators of that field’s ideas and thus identify which research streams are important and energetic (and presumably most worth pursuing) and which ones are not. This chapter thus provides an overview of the field by considering what we would include in two hypothetical JDM handbooks, one published in 1974 and one published in 1988. We attempt to identify which topics were viewed as the major questions and main developments at the time of those handbooks. In so doing, we reveal how the field has evolved, identifying research areas that have more or less always been central to the field as well as those that have declined in importance. For the latter topics, we speculate about reasons for their decreased prominence.

    Our chapter’s organization complements more traditional historical accounts of the field. Many reviews of this sort have appeared over the years in Annual Review of Psychology (e.g., Becker & McClintock, 1967; Edwards, 1961; Einhorn & Hogarth, 1981; Gigerenzer & Gaissmaier, 2011; Hastie, 2001; Lerner, Li, Valdesolo, & Kassam, 2015; Lopes, 1994; Mellers Schwartz, & Cooke, 1998; Oppenheimer & Kelso, 2015; Payne, Bettman, & Johnson, 1992; Pitz & Sachs, 1984; Rapoport & Wallsten, 1972; Shafir & LeBoeuf, 2002; Slovic, Fischhoff, & Lichtenstein, 1977; E. U. Weber & Johnson, 2009). In addition, excellent reviews appear as chapters in various non-JDM handbooks (Abelson & Levi, 1985; Ajzen, 1996; Dawes, 1998; Fischhoff, 1988; Gilovich & Griffin, 2010; Markman & Medin, 2002; Payne, Bettman, & Luce, 1998; Russo & Carlson, 2002; Slovic, Lichtenstein, & Fischhoff, 1988; Stevenson, Busemeyer, & Naylor, 1990); in W. M. Goldstein and Hogarth’s (1997) excellent historical introduction to their collection of research papers; and in textbooks, such as Bazerman and Moore (2012), Hastie and Dawes (2010), Hogarth (1987), Plous (1993), von Winterfeldt and Edwards (1986, pp. 560–574), and Yates (1990).

    We have divided 60 years of JDM research into four Handbook periods: 1954–1972, 1972–1986, 1986–2002, and 2002–2014. The first period (1954–1972) marks the initiation of several systematic research lines of JDM, many of which are still central to this day. Most notably, Edwards introduced microeconomic theory to psychologists and thus set up a dichotomy between the normative and descriptive perspectives on decision making. This dichotomy remains at the heart of much of JDM research. The second period (1972–1986) is characterized by several new developments, the most significant ones being the launching of the heuristics and biases research program (Kahneman, Slovic, & Tversky 1982) and the introduction of prospect theory (Kahneman & Tversky, 1979). In the third period (1986–2002), we see the infusion of influences such as emotion, motivation, and culture from other areas of psychology into JDM research, as well as the rapid spread of JDM ideas into areas such as economics, marketing, and social psychology. This period was covered by Koehler and Harvey’s (2004) handbook. In the last period (2002–2014), JDM has continued to develop as a multidisciplinary field in ways that are at least partially reflected by the increased application of JDM research to domains such as business, medicine, law, and public policy.

    The present introductory chapter is organized as follows. We first discuss some important early milestones in the field. This discussion attempts to identify the underlying scholarly threads that broadly define the field and thus situates the selection of topics for our four periods. In the next two sections, we outline the contents of two editions of the hypothetical Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making one published roughly in 1974 (to cover 1954–1972) and one published roughly in 1988 (to cover 1972–1986).² As noted, the period from 1986–2002 is covered in Koehler and Harvey’s 2004 handbook and the last period is roughly covered in the present two volumes. We also discuss these two periods and comment on how the contents of these two handbooks reflect the field in 2004 and 2015, respectively. In the final section, we conclude with some broader thoughts about how the field has changed over the last 60 years. Speculations about what future directions the field might take are briefly presented in the final chapter.

    Some Early Historical Milestones

    Several points in time could be considered as marking the inception of judgment and decision making. One possible starting point may be Pascal’s wager: the French philosopher Blaise Pascal’s formulation of the decision problem in which humans bet on whether to believe in God’s existence (Pascal, 1670). This proposal can be thought of as the first attempt to perform an expected utility (hereafter, throughout the handbook, EU) analysis on an existential problem and to employ probabilistic reasoning in an uncertain context. Two other natural candidates are Bernoulli’s (1738/1954) famous paper Exposition of a New Theory of Measurement of Risk, which introduced the notion of diminishing marginal utility, and Bentham’s (1879) book An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, which proposed some dimensions of pleasure and pain, two major sources of utility (see Stigler, 1950). Because neither of these works had much explicit psychological discussion (but see Kahneman, Wakker, & Sarin, 1997 which discusses some of Bentham’s psychological insights), a more natural starting point is the publication of Ward Edwards’s (1954) seminal article The Theory of Decision Making, in Psychological Bulletin, which can be viewed as an introduction to microeconomic theory written for psychologists. The topics of that influential paper included riskless choice (i.e., consumer theory), risky choice, subjective probability, and the theory of games, with the discussion of these topics interspersed with a series of psychological comments. The article’s most essential exhortation is encapsulated in the paper’s final sentence: all these topics represent a new and rich field for psychologists, in which a theoretical structure has already been elaborately worked out and in which many experiments need to be performed (p. 411). Edwards followed up this article in 1961 with the publication of Behavioral Decision Theory in the Annual Review of Psychology. That paper should be seen as a successor to the 1954 article as well as evidence for the earlier paper’s enormous influence: This review covers the same subject matter for the period 1954 through April, 1960 (p. 473). The tremendous volume of empirical and theoretical research on decision making in those six years speaks to the remarkable growth of the emerging field of judgment and decision making.

    Two other important publications also marked the introduction of JDM: Savage’s (1954) The Foundations of Statistics and Luce and Raiffa’s (1957) Games and Decisions. These two books cover the three major theories that dominated the field at its inception: utility theory, probability theory, and game theory. A major query regarding each of the three theories concerned the extent to which they had a normative (what should people do) or a descriptive (what do people actually do) orientation. All three theories were originally conceived as normative in that they contained recommendations for the best possible decisions, a view that reflected a tacit endorsement that human decision making is undertaken by homo economicus, an individual who strictly follows the rational rules dictated by logic and mathematics (Mill, 1836).³ Deviations were thought to be incidental (i.e., errors of performance) rather than systematic (e.g., errors of comprehension).

    Edwards (1954) made clear that actual behavior might depart from the normative standard and inspired a generation of scholars to question the descriptive validity of these theories. Indeed, one of the hallmarks of the newborn discipline of judgment and decision making was the conceptual and empirical interplay between the normative and the descriptive facets of various judgment and decision making theories. This interplay played an essential role in the development of the field and remains central to the field to this day.

    Both probability and utility theory (and to some extent game theory; see, e.g., Nash, 1950) are founded on axiomatic systems. An axiomatic system is a set of conditions (i.e., axioms) that are necessary and sufficient for a particular theory. As such, they are useful for normative purposes (individuals can reflect on whether an axiom is a reasonable principle; see Raiffa, 1968; Slovic & Tversky, 1974) as well as descriptive purposes (an axiom often provides a clear recipe for testing a theory; see the discussion of the Allais Paradox later in this chapter). Luce and Raiffa (1957) identified some gaps between the normative and descriptive facets of EU theory. For each of von Neumann and Morgenstern’s (1947) axioms, they provided some critical comments questioning the validity of that axiom and examining its behavioral applicability to real-life situations. For instance, the discussion of the reduction of compound lotteries axiom foreshadowed later experimental research that established systematic violations of that axiom (Bar-Hillel, 1973; Ronen, 1971). Similarly, doubts about the transitivity axiom anticipated research that demonstrated that preferences can cycle (e.g., Tversky, 1969). These reservations were small in force relative to the more fundamental critique levied by Maurice Allais’ famous counterexample to the descriptive validity of EU theory (Allais, 1953). The Allais Paradox, along with the Ellsberg (1961) Paradox, continues to spawn research in the JDM literature (see Chapters 2 and 3 of the present handbook).

    Somewhat later, a stream of research with a similar spirit explored whether subjective probability assessments differed from the probabilities dictated by the axioms of probability theory. The research in the early 1960s, much of it conducted by Edwards and his colleagues, was devoted to probability judgments and their assessments. Edwards, Lindman, and Savage (1963) introduced the field of psychology to Bayesian reasoning, and indeed a great deal of that research examined whether humans were Bayesian in assessing probabilities. A number of early papers suggested that the answer was generally no (Peterson & Miller, 1965; Phillips & Edwards, 1966; Phillips, Hays, & Edwards, 1966). Descendants of this work are still at the center of JDM (see Chapter 6 in this handbook).

    The study of discrepancies between formal normative models and actual human behavior marked the beginning of the field and has served as a tempting target for empirical work. Indeed, according to Phillips and von Winterfeldt (2007), 139 papers testing the empirical validity of EU theory appeared between 1954 and 1961. Although the contrast between normative and descriptive remains a major theme underlying JDM research today, most JDM researchers strive to go beyond documenting a discrepancy to providing a psychological explanation for that phenomenon. Simon (1956) provided one early and influential set of ideas that have shaped the field’s theorizing about psychological mechanisms. He proposed that humans satisfice or adapt to their environment by seeking a satisfactory rather than optimal decision. This adaptive notion anticipated several research programs, including Kahneman and Tversky’s influential heuristics and biases program (Kahneman & Tversky, 1974).

    It is also worth noting that the field was an interdisciplinary one from the beginning. Edwards had a visible role in this development by bringing economic theory and models to psychology, a favor that psychologists would return years later in the development of the field of behavioral economics. The interdisciplinary nature of the field was also reflected in monographs such as Decision Making: An Experimental Approach (1957), a collaboration between the philosopher Donald Davidson, the philosopher and mathematician Patrick Suppes, and the psychologist Sidney Siegel. The clear ubiquity and importance of decision making also meant that the application of JDM ideas included fields ranging from business and law to medicine and meteorology.

    We next turn to the contents of our four handbooks, two hypothetical and two actual. Although these handbooks illustrate the growth and development of the field over the last 60 years, we also see throughout the interplay between the normative standard and descriptive reality, as well as the interdisciplinary nature of the field.

    The Initial Period, 1954–1972 (Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making, 1974)

    The period from 1954 to 1972 can be viewed as the one in which the discipline of behavioral decision making went through its initial development. As we will see, many of the questions posed during that period continue to shape research today. By 1972, the field had an identity, with many scholars describing themselves as judgment and decision making researchers. In 1969, a Research Conference on Subjective Probability and Related Fields took place in Hamburg, Germany. In 1971, that conference, in its third iteration, had changed its name to the Research Conference on Subjective Probability, Utility, and Decision Making (or SPUDM for short), hence broadening the scope of that organization and reflecting in some respects the maturation of the field. SPUDM has taken place every second year since that date (see Vlek, 1999, for a history of SPUDM).

    Suppose, in retrospect, that we were transported back in time to 1972 or so and tasked with preparing a handbook of judgment and decision making. How would such a volume be structured and how does the current volume differ from such a hypothetical volume? Figure 1.1 contains a list of contents of such a volume, retrospectively assembled by the two of us. In preparing this list, we have assumed the role of hypothetical curators, with the caveat that other researchers would likely have constructed a different list.⁵

    c1-fig-0001

    Figure 1.1 Contents of a hypothetical JDM handbook for the period 1954–1972.

    As the previous section indicated, three major themes have attracted the attention of JDM researchers since the inception of the field and continue to serve as the backbones of the field to varying extents even today: uncertainty and probability theory; decision under risk and utility theory; and strategic decision making and game theory. Accordingly, three sections in Figure 1.1 correspond to these three major pillars of the field.

    Our first hypothetical volume contains an introductory chapter (Chapter 1, 1974) that presents an overview of the normative versus descriptive distinction, a distinction that had been central to the field since its inception. (We denote the chapters with the publication date of that hypothetical or actual handbook because we at times will refer to earlier or later handbooks; references to the hypothetical works are given in bold.) The Handbook then consists of four parts:

    Uncertainty;

    Choice behavior;

    Game theory and its applications;

    Other topics.

    Hundreds of volumes have been written on the topic of uncertainty. For physicists and philosophers, the major question is whether uncertainty is inherent in nature. The development of the normative treatment of uncertainty as in modern probability theory is described in Hacking’s (1975) stimulating book. Researchers in JDM, however, assume that uncertainty is a reflection of the human mind and hence subjective. Accordingly, the second part of our imaginary volume is devoted to the assessment of uncertainty.

    Chapter 2 (1974) serves as an introduction to this part and contrasts objective or frequentist notions of probability with subjective or personalistic probabilities. In a series of studies, John Cohen and his colleagues (J. Cohen, 1964, 1972; J. Cohen & Hansel, 1956) studied the relationship between subjective probability and gambling behavior. They found violations of the basic principles of probability such as evidence of the gambler’s fallacy. Indeed, Cohen’s work anticipated Kahneman and Tversky’s heuristics and biases research program (see Chapter 3, 1988).

    Bayesian reasoning, a major research program initiated by Edwards (1962) (see also Edwards, Lindman, & Savage, 1963) is the topic of Chapter 3 (1974). This program was motivated by understanding whether people’s estimates and intuitions are compatible with the Bayesian model, as well as whether the Bayesian model can serve as a satisfactory descriptive model for human probabilistic reasoning (Edwards, 1968). Using what has become known as the bookbag and poker chip paradigm, Edwards and his colleagues (e.g., Peterson, Schneider, & Miller, 1965; Phillips & Edwards, 1966) ran dozens of studies on how humans revise their opinions in light of new information. This research inspired Peterson and Beach (1967) to describe man as an intuitive statistician and argue that by and large statistics can be used as the basis for psychological models that integrate and account for human performance in a wide range of inferential tasks (p. 29). However, Edwards (1968) also pointed out that subjects were conservative in their updating: opinion change is very orderly … but it is insufficient in amount … [and] takes anywhere from two to five observations to do one observation’s worth of work (p. 18). The notion of man as an intuitive statistician was soon taken on by Kahneman and Tversky’s work on heuristics and biases, and the tendency toward conservatism was later challenged by Griffin and Tversky (1992) (see also Massey & Wu, 2005).

    Chapter 4 (1974) covers the distinction between clinical and statistical modes of probabilistic reasoning. In this terminology, clinical refers to case studies that are used to generate subjective estimates, while statistical reflects some actuarial analytical model. In a seminal book, which influences the field to this day, Meehl (1954; see also Dawes, Faust, & Meehl, 1989) found that clinical predictions were typically much less accurate than actuarial or statistical predictions. As noted by Einhorn (1986), the statistical models were more advantageous because they accepted error to make less error. Dawes, Faust, and Meehl (1993) reviewed 10 diverse areas of application that demonstrated the superiority of the statistical models relative to human judgment.

    Chapter 5 (1974) is devoted to the issue of probability learning (e.g., Estes, 1976). A typical probability-learning study involves a long series of trials in which subjects choose one of two actions on each trial. Each action has a different unknown probability of generating a reward. This topic was extensively studied in the 1950s and the 1960s (for an elaborate review, see Lee, 1971, Chapter 6). Researchers discovered that subjects tended toward probability matching (Grant, Hake, & Hornseth, 1951): the frequency with which a particular action is chosen matches the assessed probability that action is the preferred choice. This phenomenon has been repeatedly replicated (e.g., Gaissmaier & Schooler, 2008) and is noteworthy because human behavior is inconsistent with the optimal strategy of choosing the action with the highest probability of generating a reward.

    Chapter 6 (1974) covers estimation methods of subjective probability. Although this topic was still in its infancy, the emergence of decision analysis (see Chapter 19, 1974) emphasized the need to develop and test methods for eliciting probabilities. Some of the early work in that area was conducted by Alpert and Raiffa (1982; study conducted in 1968), Murphy and Winkler (1970), Savage (1971), Staël von Holstein (1970, 1971), and Winkler (1967a, 1967b). More comprehensive overviews of elicitation methods are found in later reviews, such as Spetzler and Staël von Holstein (1975) and Wallsten and Budescu (1983).

    The subsequent part of our imaginary handbook is devoted to utility theories for decision under risk and uncertainty (Chapter 7, 1974). Already anticipated by Bernoulli (1738/1954) EU theory was formalized in an axiomatic system by von Neumann and Morgenstern (1947). This theory considers decision under risk, or gambles with objective probabilities such as winning $100 if a fair coin comes up heads. A later development by Savage (1954), subjective expected utility (hereafter, thoughout the handbook, SEU) theory, extended EU to more natural gambles such as winning $100 if General Electric’s stock price were to increase by over 1% in a given month. Savage’s framework thus covered decision under uncertainty, using subjective probabilities rather than the objective probabilities provided by the experimenter. Some of the early research in utility theory was an attempt to eliminate the gap between the normative and the descriptive. For example, Friedman and Savage (1948) famously attempted to explain the simultaneous purchase of lottery tickets (a risk-seeking activity) and insurance (a risk-averse activity) by positing a utility function with many inflection points. Many years later, the lottery-ticket-purchasing gambler would be a motivation for Kahneman and Tversky’s (1979) prospect theory, an explicitly descriptive account of how individuals choose among risky gambles (see also Tversky & Kahneman, 1992).

    This line of research embraced what has become known as the gambling metaphor or the gambling paradigm. Research participants were posed with a set of (usually two) hypothetical gambles to choose between. The gambles were generally described by well-defined probabilities of receiving well-defined (and generally) monetary outcomes. The gambling metaphor presumed that most real-world risky decisions reflected a balance between likelihood and value, and that hypothetical choices of the sort Would you prefer $100 for sure, or a 50–50 chance at getting $250 or nothing? offered insight into the psychological processes people employed when faced with risky decisions. The strengths and limitations of the gambling paradigm are discussed in the concluding chapter of this handbook.

    Savage’s sure-thing principle and EU theory’s independence axiom constitute the cornerstones of SEU and EU, respectively. The most well-known violations of these axioms, and hence counter examples to the descriptive validity of these theories, were formulated by Allais (1953) and Ellsberg (1961) and first demonstrated in careful experiments by MacCrimmon (1968). The Allais and Ellsberg Paradoxes are described in Chapter 8 (1974), as well as other early empirical investigations of EU theory (e.g., Mosteller & Nogee, 1951; Preston & Baratta, 1948). Decision under risk and decision under uncertainty continue to be mainstream JDM topics and appear in this handbook as Chapter 2 (2015) and Chapter 3 (2015).

    Chapter 9 (1974) discusses preference reversals. Lichtenstein and Slovic (1971) documented a fascinating pattern in which individuals preferred gamble A to gamble B, but nevertheless priced B higher than A. This demonstration was an affront to normative utility theories, because it demonstrated that preferences might depend on the procedure used to elicit them. More fundamentally, this demonstration was a severe blow to the notion that individuals have well-defined preferences (Grether & Plott, 1969) and anticipated Kahneman and Tversky’s (1979) more systematic attack on procedural invariance (see Chapters 11 and 12, 1988). It also set the stage for theorizing on how context can affect attribute weights (Tversky, Sattath, & Slovic, 1988) as well as an identification of a broader class of preference reversals, such as those involving joint and separate evaluation (e.g., Chapter 18, 2004; Chapter 7, 2015) and conflict and choice (e.g., Chapter 17, 2004).

    Chapter 10 (1974) surveys measurement theory (e.g., Krantz, Luce, Suppes, & Tversky, 1971; Suppes, Krantz, Luce, & Tversky, 1989), in particular the measurement of utility. The methodological and conceptual difficulties associated with the assessment of utility were recognized at an early stage and attracted the attention of many researchers (e.g., Coombs & Bezembinder, 1967; Davidson, Suppes, & Siegel, 1957; Mosteller & Nogee, 1951). Different attempts at developing a theory of measurement have taken the form of functional (Anderson, 1970) and conjoint (Krantz & Tversky, 1971) measurement. Although measurement theory received much attention by leading researchers in psychology (e.g., Coombs, Dawes, & Tversky, 1970; Krantz, Luce, Suppes, & Tversky, 1971) the interest in these issues has declined over the years for reasons that remain unclear (e.g., Cliff, 1992). Nevertheless, we believe that measurement is still an essential issue for JDM research and hope that these topics will again receive their due attention.⁶

    The topic of Chapter 11 (1974) is psychophysics. The initial developments of psychophysical laws are commonly attributed to Gustav Theodor Fechner and Ernst Heinrich Weber (Luce, 1959). The most fundamental psychophysical principle, diminishing sensitivity, is that increased stimulation is associated with a decreasing impact. The origins of this law can be traced to Bernoulli’s (1738/1954) original exposition of utility theory and is reflected in the familiar economic notion of diminishing marginal utility in which successive additions of money (or any other commodity) yield smaller and smaller increases in value. Psychophysical research has also identified a number of other stimulus and response mode biases that influence sensory judgments (Poulton, 1979), and these biases, as well as the psychophysical principle of diminishing sensitivity, have shaped how JDM researchers have thought about the measurement of numerical quantities, whether the quantities be utility values or probabilities (von Winterfeldt & Edwards, 1986, 351–354).

    The closing Chapter 12 (1974) of this part goes beyond individual decision making and examines social choice theory (Arrow, 1954) and group decision making. Arrow’s famous Impossibility Theorem showed that there exists no method to aggregate individual preferences into a collective or group preference that satisfies some basic and appealing criterion. This work, along with others, also motivated some experimental investigation of group decision making processes. One of the first research endeavors in this area, Siegel and Fouraker (1960), involved a collaboration between a psychologist (Sidney Siegel) and an economist (Lawrence Fouraker), again reflecting the interdisciplinary nature of the field. Group decision making is covered in subsequent handbooks: Chapter 23 (2004) and Chapter 30 (2015).

    The next part of our first fictional handbook covers game theory (von Neumann & Morgenstern, 1947) and its applications. Luce and Raiffa (1957) introduced the central ideas of game theory to social scientists and made what were previously regarded as abstract mathematical ideas accessible to non mathematicians (Dodge, 2006). The same year also marked the appearance of the Journal of Conflict Resolution, a journal that became a major outlet for applications of game theory to the social sciences. In the 1950s and 1960s, game theory was seen as having enormous potential for modeling and understanding conflict resolution (e.g., Schelling, 1958, 1960).

    Schelling (1958) introduced the distinction between (a) pure-conflict (or zero sum) games in which any gain of one party is the loss of the other party; (b) mixed motives (or non-zero-sum) games, which involve conflict though one side’s gain does not necessarily constitute a loss for the other; and (c) cooperation games in which the parties involved share exactly the same goals. Chapter 13 (1974) presents the empirical research for each of these three types of games conducted in the pertinent period. Merrill Flood, a management scientist, conducted some of the earliest experimental studies (Flood, 1954, 1958). Social psychologists studied various versions of these games in the 1960s and 1970s (e.g., Messick & McClintock, 1968). Rapoport and Orwant (1962) provided a review of some of the first generation of experiments (see Rapoport, Guyer, & Gordon, 1976, for a later review).

    The prisoner’s dilemma has received more attention than any other game, with the possible recent exception of the ultimatum game, probably because of its transparent applications to many real-life situations. Chapter 14 (1974) surveys experimental research on the prisoner’s dilemma. Flood (1954) conducted perhaps the earliest study of that game, and Rapoport and Chammah (1965) and Gallo and McClintock (1965) presented a comprehensive discussion of the game and some experiments conducted to date. See also Chapter 24 (2004) and Chapter 19 (2015), as well as the large body of work on social dilemmas (e.g., Dawes, 1980).

    The final part of the handbook is devoted to several broader topics that are not unique to JDM but were seen as useful tools for understanding judgment and decision making. Chapter 15 (1974) reviews Signal Detection Theory (Swets, 1961; Swets, Tanner, & Birdsall, 1961; Green & Swets, 1966). The theory was originally applied mainly to psychophysics as an attempt to reflect the old concept of sensory thresholds with response thresholds. Swets (1961) was included in one of the earliest collection of decision making articles (Edwards & Tversky, 1967), an indication of the belief that signal detection theory would have many important applications in judgment and decision making research.

    Information theory (Shannon, 1948; Shannon & Weaver, 1949) is the topic of Chapter 16 (1974). In the second half of the twentieth century, information theory made invaluable contributions to the technological developments in fields such as engineering and computer science. As Miller (1953) noted, there was considerable fuss over something called ‘information theory,’ in particular because it was presumed to be useful in understanding judgment and decision processes under uncertainty. The great hopes of Miller and others did not materialize, and after 1970 the theory was hardly cited in the social sciences (see, however, Garner, 1974, for a classic psychological application of information theory). Luce (2003) discusses possible reasons for the decline of information theory in psychology.

    Chapter 17 (1974) describes decision analysis. Decision analysis, defined as a set of tools and techniques designed to help individuals and corporations structure and analyze their decisions, emerged in the 1960s (Howard, 1964, 1968; Raiffa, 1968; see von Winterfeldt & Edwards, 1986, 566–574, for a brief history of decision analysis). Decision analysis was soon a required course in many business schools (Schlaifer, 1969), and the promise of the field to influence decision making is reflected in the following quotation from Brown (1989): In the sixties, decision aiding was dominated by normative developments. … It was widely assumed that a sound normative structure would lead to prescriptively useful procedures (p. 468). This chapter presents an overview of decision-aiding tools such as decision trees and sensitivity analysis, as well as topics that interface more directly with JDM research, such as probability encoding (Spetzler & Staël von Holstein, 1975; see also Chapter 6, 1974) and multiattribute utility theory (Keeney & Raiffa, 1976; Raiffa, 1969; see also Chapter 14, 1988).

    The last chapter (Chapter 18, 1974) of this first handbook covers thinking and reasoning, which is included although the link with JDM had not been fully articulated in the early 1970s when our hypothetical handbook appears. The chapter discusses confirmation bias (Wason, 1960, 1968) and reasoning with negation (Wason, 1959), as well as the question of whether people are invariably logical unless they failed to accept the logical task (Henle, 1962). In some respects, Henle’s paper anticipated the question of rationality (e.g., L. J. Cohen, 1981; see Chapter 2, 1988) as well as research on hypothesis testing (Chapter 17, 1988; Chapter 10, 2004).

    Before moving on to the next period, we make several remarks about the field in the early 1970s. Although JDM has always been an interdisciplinary field and was certainly one in this early period, the orientation of the field was demonstrably more mathematical in nature, centered on normative criteria, and closer to cognitive psychology than it is today. This orientation partially reflects the topics that consumed the field at this point and the requisite comparison of empirical results with mathematical models. But another part reflects a sense at that time of the useful interplay between mathematical models and empirical research (e.g., Coombs, Raiffa, & Thrall, 1954). For a number of reasons, many of the more technical of these ideas (e.g., information theory, measurement theory, and signal detection theory) have decreased in popularity since that time. Although these topics were seen as promising in the early 1970s, they do not appear in our subsequent handbooks.

    Game theory, along with utility theory and probability theory, was one of the three major theories Edwards (1954) offered up to psychologists for empirical investigation. However, game theory has never been nearly as central to JDM as the study of risky decision making or probabilistic judgment. Chapter 19 (2015) argues that this may be partially because of conventional game theory’s focus on equilibrium concepts. The chapter proposes an alternative framework for studying strategic interactions that might be more palatable to JDM researchers (see also Camerer, 2003, for a more general synthesis of psychological principles and game-theoretic reasoning under the umbrella behavioral game theory).

    Finally, there was great hope in the early 1970s that decision-aiding tools such as decision analysis could lead individuals to make better decisions. Decision analysis has probably fallen short of that promise, partly because of the difficulty of defining what constitutes a good decision (see Chapter 34, 2015; Frisch & Clemen, 1994) and partly because of the inherent subjectivity of inputs into decision models (see Chapter 32, 2015; Clemen, 2008). Although the connection between decision analysis and judgment decision making has become more tenuous since the mid-1980s, it nevertheless remains an important topic for the JDM community and is covered in Chapter 32 (2015).⁷,⁸

    The Second Period (1972–1986) (Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making, 1988)

    Our second imaginary handbook covers approximately the period 1972–1986. This period reflects several new research programs that are still at the heart

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1