Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Natural Theology: The Metaphysics of God
Natural Theology: The Metaphysics of God
Natural Theology: The Metaphysics of God
Ebook269 pages10 hours

Natural Theology: The Metaphysics of God

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

In this book my sole aim is to present clearly and succinctly for students some central arguments and truths about God in so far as He is known to us in the light of reason. This pedagogical purpose dictates a great deal of compression, lest the student be lost in a labyrinth of dialectical and historical discussion, however important that may be in itself. But compression need not mean oversimplification. It does mean condensing, abridging, epitomizing. This has been done deliberately, in the interest of the student.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateMay 19, 2020
ISBN9781839745188
Natural Theology: The Metaphysics of God
Author

James F. Anderson

James F. Anderson is associate professor in the Biology department at Marquette University.

Related to Natural Theology

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Natural Theology

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Natural Theology - James F. Anderson

    © Barakaldo Books 2020, all rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted by any means, electrical, mechanical or otherwise without the written permission of the copyright holder.

    Publisher’s Note

    Although in most cases we have retained the Author’s original spelling and grammar to authentically reproduce the work of the Author and the original intent of such material, some additional notes and clarifications have been added for the modern reader’s benefit.

    We have also made every effort to include all maps and illustrations of the original edition the limitations of formatting do not allow of including larger maps, we will upload as many of these maps as possible.

    NATURAL THEOLOGY — THE METAPHYSICS OF GOD

    BY

    JAMES F. ANDERSON

    Professor of Philosophy

    Villanova University

    TABLE OF CONTENTS

    Contents

    TABLE OF CONTENTS 4

    DEDICATION 5

    Preface 6

    Note on Readings and Bibliography 8

    Abbreviations 9

    PART ONE—The Existence of God 10

    CHAPTER I—Prolegomena 10

    READINGS 25

    CHAPTER II—Arguments in Proof of God’s Existence 27

    Appendix to Chapter II—THE FIVE WAYS OF ST. THOMAS (ST, I, q. 2, a. 3) 52

    READINGS 55

    PART TWO—The Nature of God, or: The Manner of His Existence 58

    CHAPTER III—Entitative Attributes of God: Names Signifying His Being 58

    CHAPTER IV—The Operative Attributes of God 89

    Bibliography 127

    A. Ancient and Medieval 127

    B. Early Modern 128

    C. Late Modern and Contemporary 128

    APPENDIX 135

    Note on the Relation Between Revealed Theology and Metaphysics 135

    REQUEST FROM THE PUBLISHER 138

    DEDICATION

    TO

    OUR LADY

    SEAT OF WISDOM

    Preface

    In this book my sole aim is to present clearly and succinctly for students some central arguments and truths about God in so far as He is known to us in the light of reason. This pedagogical purpose dictates a great deal of compression, lest the student be lost in a labyrinth of dialectical and historical discussion, however important that may be in itself. But compression need not mean oversimplification. It does mean condensing, abridging, epitomizing. This has been done deliberately, in the interest of the student.

    Moreover, an effort has been made throughout to engage the student directly; hence the large number of questions addressed to him. Is not the object of all teaching to engage the minds of others, so that they will share the teacher’s knowledge? In this case, fortunately, the chief teacher is not myself, but Thomas Aquinas. But note well that his teachings are proposed not because they are, or are thought to be, his, but because they are, or are thought to be, true. In other words, we appeal to him not as an arbitrary authority, but as a reliable guide. Would not an Aristotelian, a Cartesian, a Kantian, a Whiteheadian, have to say or imply the same thing concerning a similar work of his own?

    Still, the question remains: why go to Thomas for philosophical instruction about God? For Catholics the answer is simply that the Church recommends him above all other teachers, not only in theology, but also in philosophy. But that instruction, for Catholics as well as for everyone else, must stand or fall on the evidence of reason alone. This point should be kept clearly in mind by all of us. Does not St. Thomas himself say that the argument based on human authority is the weakest of all?{1}

    Nevertheless, it is entirely reasonable to ask why non-Catholics should be invited to go to Thomas for philosophical instruction. Doubtless there are many good reasons for issuing such an invitation. One of them is this: the centuries-old recognition—not confined to the Catholic or even the Christian world—that Thomas Aquinas has much to say about things philosophical that is valid and true for all men on grounds of reason alone.

    In this book, then, as in every book that purports to be philosophical, the ultimate appeal must be to reason. Reason, however, does not exist in the abstract, but only in men’s minds. That is why every philosopher is necessarily following the guidance—more or less closely, and whether wittingly or not—of some other philosopher or philosophers. In this there are many varying preferences, not necessarily exclusive of one another. But whatever the preference may be, the decisive thing in philosophy is always that the truth of the doctrine or of the argument depends entirely on the weight of the rational evidence adduced in its support.

    It is a pleasure to acknowledge my indebtedness to my friend from Marquette University, Father Gerard Smith, S.J., whose metaphysical wit is matched by his metaphysical wisdom. (See especially his great book, Natural Theology [New York: Macmillan, 1951].) Thanks also are due to my colleague, the editor of this Series, Professor Donald A. Gallagher, for his many helpful suggestions; to Mr. William May of the Bruce Publishing Company, for his patient editorial labors; to Mr. Donald J. Inverso, graduate assistant in philosophy, for preparing the index; and to Mrs. Helen Stoughton, without whose competent typing services, provided by Villanova University, this book would not have gone to press at this time.

    Note on Readings and Bibliography

    Both the Readings for the individual Chapters and the Bibliography at the end of the book are drawn up with the modern English-speaking student in mind. The shortness of time usually allotted to the course in natural theology dictates economy in the number of references. The Bibliography, though limited to a relatively small number of works in English, contains some additional items to which the professor may wish to refer his students.

    For discussion and presentation of some invalid philosophical arguments for God’s existence, the student may profitably read in order: Gilson’s History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages, p. 130 ff., Descartes’ Meditations, Nos. 3 and 5, Gilson’s God and Philosophy, pp. 74-91, Leibniz’ Monadology, No. 40, Spinoza’s Ethics, Pt. 1, props. 7 and 11; Maritain’s The Degrees of Knowledge, Ch. 4, sec. 3, p. 186 f., note 3.

    Concerning the age-old and yet modern problem of agnosticism in this connection—viz., the doctrine that the human reason is of itself unable to establish the existence of God—the student may well read: Gilson’s History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages, pp. 487-497, Maritain’s Three Reformers, pp. 3-50, Gilson’s God and Philosophy, pp. 109-144, his The Unity of Philosophical Experience, pp. 221-270, along with Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Bk. 2, Ch. 3, secs. 3-7, James’s Pragmatism, p. 54 ff., and Bergmann’s article, Logical Positivism, in A History of Philosophical Systems.

    For a good general introduction to modern existentialism and the problem of proving God’s existence see Kuhn’s article, Existentialism, in A History of Philosophical Systems, p. 406 ff., and Wahl’s A Short History of Existentialism, p. 9 ff.

    Concerning atheism in its various forms, the student is urged to read Maritain’s essay, The Meaning of Contemporary Atheism, in The Range of Reason, p. 103 ff., and De Lubac’s book, The Drama of Atheistic Humanism.

    The foregoing issues, and others akin to them, are of vital significance in the whole area of man’s intellectual and moral life. They are vitally significant for the metaphysical science called Natural Theology. But they presuppose a basic and solid, if introductory, understanding of the positive teaching of that science. So difficult is it to provide such an introduction within the limits of a one-semester course, that inclusion of such issues in the course proper would only impede that primary task.

    The Appendices to An Introduction to Natural Theology by M. R. Holloway, S.J., contain useful summaries in several of those areas. The readings recommended previously could well be the subjects of special assignments.

    Abbreviations

    ST: Summa Theologiae of St. Thomas Aquinas

    SCG: Summa Contra Gentiles of St. Thomas Aquinas

    PL: Patrologia Latina

    PG: Patrologia Graeca

    PART ONE—The Existence of God

    CHAPTER I—Prolegomena

    Sec. 1. Pre-Philosophical Knowledge of God

    Of all the myriad thoughts that have preoccupied men through the ages there is one that stands out above all others: the idea of God. Is it by accident that the history of man’s life and culture is in large part the history of this idea? Can the existence of such a universal phenomenon be a matter of chance?

    Is it not clear, on the contrary, that a thing regularly recurrent can be explained only in the light of some causal constancy? Wherein does the intelligibility of such a thing consist if not in its being the effect of a principle providing an essential orientation?

    Now this principle obviously is something within man himself—part and parcel of his humanity. This principle is nothing other than the natural bent of man’s mind toward that which ultimately is.

    Here we face a most remarkable fact: the presence throughout human history of ideas and questions and concerns about God. These indeed do not prove that He really exists; but they do prove that the human mind has an inborn proclivity toward this kind of thinking. Again, if one asks why that is so, one will find the basic reason in the nature of the God-thinking subject: man, an animal endowed with intellectuality. For man is a theologizing animal just because he is a rational animal.

    Consider what it means to have an intellect. It means possessing a power for knowing in some way whatever in any way is. Nothing lies wholly outside its range; the simply unknowable simply is not. An intellect—even the lowly human one—has of its very nature an infinite scope or field of operation; it is essentially the faculty of being; it is essentially open to all that is.{2}

    Let us reflect for a moment upon this intellective faculty that is naturally endowed with the capacity for knowing universal being. Note the comparison with our faculty of vision: just as sight includes within its scope all that is colored, so intellect extends to all that is. Its adequate object is literally what it is by nature equal to, namely, universal being. Whatever is is of itself intelligible; whatever is is a possible object of knowledge just because and in so far as it is.

    We have noted the presence in the human mind of a natural aptitude for some consideration of ultimate common or universal being and of the cause of being, God, who is being in the ultimate sense. And He is knowable as such a cause. But of this we must distinguish two levels: the one pre-philosophical, non-reflexive, instinctive, so to speak; the other formally philosophical, reflexive, logically elaborated. These two ways of thinking of God are necessarily present because the relation between them is like the relation of matter to form. The instinctive, natural knowledge of God constitutes the matter for the reflexive, logically elaborated knowledge of Him. Since form is in no case elicited from or put into matter without the matter’s being present, it is clear that a certain pre-philosophical knowledge of God is the indispensable matter out of which some formally philosophical knowledge of Him may be developed. How can something be actualized if there is no potential—no matter—to start with?

    Precisely what is this pre-philosophical knowledge of God? As was said, the human intellect is a power made for knowing what is, i.e., for knowing being. But if God is pure Being, then the human intellect is made for knowing God. In that case, knowledge of God would be literally natural to the human intellect.

    On this point St. Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) is in agreement with all the great Christian doctors from Tertullian to Anselm, on down to the present. Allow me to sketch some highlights of the history of this doctrine of the natural knowledge of God.

    Among the early Christian Apologists, we find a strong insistence that a spontaneous knowledge of God is common to all men, including pagans. Tertullian (160-240), for example, says expressly that a certain knowledge of God is a primordial endowment of man’s soul.{3} And in a celebrated text he exclaims: O testimony of the soul, which is by natural instinct Christian.{4} The soul is naturally Christian, he goes on to say, even though it is bound in the prison house of the body, even though it is ensnared by untrue opinions, victimized by false learning; indeed it remains naturally Christian even though weakened by lust and concupiscence and chained to false gods. For when the soul revives, Tertullian continues, when it awakens as from intoxication or sleep or some sickness and enjoys health again, then it utters the unique name of God, because it is He alone who is, properly speaking, the one, true Being.

    There is likewise the witness of the ancient Church Fathers. St. Irenaeus (c. 126-c. 193/211), for instance, asks rhetorically{5} how it could be possible for any creatures to be ignorant of God, seeing that they all exist in Him and from Him and are all contained by Him. Irenaeus explains that God, though invisible by reason of His eminence, could never be unknown to men because of the manifestations of His providence; the divine rule clearly extends to all things. And that is why the natural reason with which we are endowed moves us to know that there is one God, the Lord of all things.{6}

    In similar vein, Clement of Alexandria (c. 150-c. 202/215) explains{7} that in all men there are certain seeds of divinity by virtue of which they are impelled to think God as first cause and ruler of all things.

    St. Cyprian (c. 200-258), too, puts this same point very forcefully: people in general naturally acknowledge the existence of God. Why, he asks, is this so? He replies that the reason is precisely because it is God Himself who is the author and source of man’s mind and soul. And he declares in a striking passage that it is the very height of transgression for men to be unwilling to recognize Him whom they cannot possibly ignore.{8}

    And then there is the telling remark of St. Jerome (c. 340-420): the knowledge of God is naturally present in all men because it is impossible for anyone to be born without Christ, even as it is impossible not to have in oneself the seeds of wisdom and of justice and of the other virtues.{9}

    But among the early Church Fathers we find in St. Augustine (354-430) the most powerful witness to this truth. To cite but one sharp text among many others, there is Augustine’s statement, in his splendid commentary on St. John’s Gospel{10}, that God could not possibly be hidden altogether from any creature having the use of reason because He is, quite apart from any revelation whatever, naturally known to all men as the author of the world.

    Passing on to the great medieval thinkers, we find (amidst innumerable significant divergencies) a remarkable unanimity on this matter of a natural knowledge of God. Their explanations varied, and varied widely; their factual assertion on this point remained the same. Let me cite a few examples.

    St. John Damascene (c. 700-c. 765) laid it down that "the knowledge of God’s existence is naturally placed (inserta) in us all by God Himself."{11} And some three hundred years later we find St. Anselm (1033-1109) drawing a conclusion which he considered to be ultimately and necessarily implied by this naturalness of man’s knowledge of God’s existence, namely, that His nonexistence is truly unthinkable.{12}

    Among the scholastics of the High Middle Ages there developed a large body of doctrine concerning the naturalness and spontaneity of such knowledge, along with various explanations of its obscure and conceptually indistinct character. Alexander of Hales (c. 1186-1245), for example, taught this doctrine,{13} as did the teacher of Thomas Aquinas, St. Albert the Great (1206-1280);{14} so too did Thomas’ contemporary St. Bonaventure (1221-1274);{15} and the subtle Doctor, Duns Scotus (1266-1308), even went so far as to say that in knowing any being whatever, and in knowing it as it is, God Himself is being conceived, albeit most indistinctly.{16}

    St. Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) agrees with all the great Christian doctors on the fact of man’s having some natural knowledge of God.{17} In the admission of this fact, however, he sees a real difficulty. For if, as St. John Damascene said, the knowledge of God’s existence is naturally implanted in us all, does this not mean that such knowledge is not acquired, but innate? And if it is really innate, then is it not self-evident?{18} In that case would we not be driven to St. Anselm’s conclusion that God’s nonexistence is unthinkable? The fact of formal atheism, however, makes that conclusion untenable!

    St. Thomas’ solution is this: God’s existence is in itself self-evident because His essence is His existence. And this is, to his mind, the true meaning of Anselm’s insistence upon the inconceivability of God’s not being. Aquinas adds, however, that God’s existence is not self-evident to us, who do not see His essence, although the knowledge of His existence is said to be innate in us inasmuch as it is possible for us to come to know, through principles which are innate in us, that God exists.{19}

    What are these natural principles which enable us to apprehend God’s existence? The first of them is the intellect itself—a faculty natively apt for knowing, somehow, whatever is.{20} It is sufficient to consider here only this one primary natural innate principle. What is called the habit of first principles, whereby the basic axioms or presuppositions of all thought are known, especially the principle of noncontradiction, is another such principle. But we need not be concerned with it presently.

    No doubt a general and indeterminate knowledge of God’s existence is for that reason innate in us.{21} No doubt, too, that the first and final reason for this is that God Himself is alone man’s beatitude, man’s fulfillment, man’s ultimate good. Man naturally desires this Good; he cannot not desire it, even though he seek it in the wrong things. But whatever a man naturally desires is naturally known by him; desire of an object presupposes some knowledge of it. St. Thomas nevertheless makes it clear that such a natural and, so to speak, instinctive knowledge of God’s existence is not equivalent to knowing absolutely that God exists, just as to know that someone is approaching is not the same as to know that Peter is approaching, even though it is Peter who is approaching.{22}

    Indeed, the scholastics generally seem to have admitted that some idea of God naturally arises from the spontaneous activity of our minds. Since this idea expresses God only in function of our most general spiritual tendencies, the knowledge it gives of Him remains obscure and indistinct. This is an authentic, though a pre-philosophical, way of knowing Him, not a conceptually determinate one. It is only subsequently, through philosophical reflection, that God is conceived of distinctly as utterly transcending the world of caused those things which are better known to us, although they are, in themselves, less evident. being. Man’s vague, indeterminate notion of divinity thus provides the matter" out of which a properly philosophical conception of God in His unique subsistence can be developed. But note that it is this obscure primordial notion of some ultimate being which makes it possible for us to exclude progressively, through categorical judgments, all that does not truly appertain to God. The fact should be emphasized, moreover, that such an obscure idea of God is not the result of a formal inference. On the contrary, it issues from a perfectly spontaneous reflection of the mind upon its basic tendencies. Man desires God first of all in a universal, indeterminate manner (in communi), as Thomas remarks. For he naturally seeks the fulfillment of his proper being, which is his perfection or goodness.{23}

    Indeed, St. Thomas explains that all things naturally desire God implicitly, though not all desire Him explicitly. Let us follow carefully the reasoning leading to this conclusion.

    A secondary or derivative cause truly exerts causality in producing an effect. But it does so only in so far as it receives the power of the appropriate primary cause. Now, just as the causality of an agent consists in action, so that of an end is to elicit appetite and desire. But the secondary agent acts only through the power of the primary agent present in it. In the same way, the secondary end is desired only through the power of the primary end present in it. In other words, a secondary end is desired or aimed at only inasmuch as it is ordered to that primary end or possesses its likeness. Because He is the absolutely first Agent, God acts in every agent, and because He is the ultimate end, He is desired in every secondary end.

    True enough, to desire God in this manner (i.e., through desiring or aiming at secondary ends) is to desire Him implicitly. But this is really to desire Him, because the power of the first Cause is present in the second cause as principles are present in conclusions. Now, it is clear that only a rational power is capable of resolving or analyzing conclusions into principles. That is why only a being endowed with reason is able to refer secondary ends to God Himself. That is also why such a being alone can desire God explicitly.{24}

    St. Thomas in fact holds that the appetite of a rational creature is not rightly ordered except through the explicit appetite of God Himself.

    Let us recall that the power of intellect has as its specific end the knowledge of being in whatever possesses it.{25} But to

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1